"How do we truly know what we know, and can we trust the beliefs we hold?”

1. Knowledge is Generated, Not Discovered

Knowledge doesn’t just exist passively in the world; it requires a knower to bring it into being. Facts, like whether a coin in a box has landed heads or tails, are meaningless unless observed and acknowledged. This transforms facts into knowledge.

The distinction between belief and knowledge is significant yet often overlooked. While some might argue that believing in something strongly enough may count as knowing, philosophers have long debated whether true knowledge can exist apart from belief. Ancient thinkers like Protagoras even questioned whether truth is subjective or universal. These discussions show how knowledge is more than mere data—it’s tied to human engagement.

Philosophical heavyweights often differ in how they define knowledge, but many agree on one point: knowledge must be supported by confidence in truth. If knowing were arbitrary or subjective, it would be impossible to have shared understandings of reality.

Examples

  • The existence of a coin landing heads-up isn't "known" until someone opens the box and sees it.
  • A weather report claiming rain becomes knowledge when it aligns with actual observation.
  • Protagoras’s argument about truth being subjective suggests that two people can “know” contradictory things based on their perceptions.

2. Skeptics Challenge What We Think We Know

Skeptics push us to question even the simplest truths. Are you wearing shoes right now? How can you be sure you’re not dreaming or hallucinating, tricked by your own perceptions? This line of inquiry exposes how tenuous much of our so-called knowledge really is.

Two ancient schools of skepticism had differing takes: Academic skeptics declared that knowledge was unattainable, while Pyrrhonian skeptics refused to take a stance on whether knowledge was possible at all. Their refusal to draw conclusions was itself a philosophical strategy to maintain open-mindedness.

While skepticism may seem impractical, it plays a vital role in reminding us to interrogate the foundations of our beliefs. The challenges presented by skeptics force us to consider whether knowledge, as we understand it, is ever truly attainable.

Examples

  • Sextus Empiricus’s catchphrase, “Perhaps it is and perhaps it is not,” epitomizes the Pyrrhonian attitude.
  • Ancient Academic skeptics argued against trusting even seemingly reliable sensory information.
  • The Stoics distinguished impressions from judgments, raising doubts about whether we ever fully judge correctly.

3. Rationalism vs. Empiricism: Two Philosophical Pathways

The debate between rationalists like Rene Descartes and empiricists like John Locke offers two distinct ways to approach knowledge. Descartes argued that certain truths are innate, such as the existence of the self and God, which he viewed as perfect concepts beyond human creation.

Locke, in contrast, dismissed the idea of innate knowledge. Instead, he argued that all understanding stems from sensory experience and reflection, developing over time. This perspective suggests that our environment and life experiences shape what we know.

These opposing perspectives highlight how different assumptions about human nature lead to very different conclusions about the origins of knowledge. They also set the stage for centuries of philosophical debate.

Examples

  • Descartes’ famous declaration, “I think, therefore I am,” suggests self-awareness is fundamental knowledge.
  • Locke observed that infants display no signs of innate rational principles.
  • Descartes believed numbers and geometry existed independently of our experiences, opposing Locke’s emphasis on learning through sensation.

4. The Slippery Line Between Belief and Knowledge

The relationship between what we believe and what we know is like a puzzle. A classical analysis proposes that knowledge requires three elements: facts, belief, and justification. But real-world scenarios often show this isn’t enough.

One example is Bertrand Russell’s clock puzzle—if a man believes it’s 1:17 based on a broken clock’s reading, does he truly know the time? This shows belief can be justified and still lead to errors. Further complications appear in Edmund Gettier’s work, which demonstrated that justified true belief doesn’t always mean knowledge.

Philosophers continue refining theories to clarify this tricky relationship, but no analysis perfectly covers all situations.

Examples

  • Russell’s clock puzzle challenges whether justified belief equals knowledge.
  • Gettier’s examples reveal how faulty information can accidentally lead to correct conclusions.
  • Alvin Goldman’s causal knowledge theory emphasizes the importance of a direct link between belief and fact.

5. Everyday Facts Aren’t as Simple as They Seem

Mount Everest is famously described as the world’s tallest mountain, but how do we know this? Externalist philosophers argue that being exposed to a factual relationship is enough to “know” it. Internalists, however, maintain that evidence and reasoning are required.

This distinction leads to endless debates. Externalists might accept the claim “Everest is the tallest” as valid knowledge without investigating further. Internalists would question this assumption, arguing that eyewitness accounts or empirical measurements are needed before accepting such a fact.

Even the most basic “truths” face scrutiny in epistemology, demonstrating how our understanding of knowledge shifts depending on how we frame evidence and belief.

Examples

  • Externalists think common knowledge, like Everest’s height, doesn’t need personal investigation.
  • Internalists challenge people to justify knowing Everest is the tallest mountain.
  • Disputes over Australia’s capital—Sydney vs. Canberra—show how widely accepted “facts” can be wrong.

6. Learning From Others: Testimony As Knowledge

Most of what we “know” about history or current events comes from secondary sources rather than direct experience. Does that mean this knowledge is invalid? Philosophers are divided on whether testimony alone can count as reliable knowledge.

Reductionists argue we can evaluate the truth of testimony using tools like perception or inference. Others go further, asserting that truthful testimony can be accepted at face value, even if the speaker doesn’t personally believe what they’re saying.

These debates demonstrate just how much of our world relies on secondhand sources and the challenges involved in determining their reliability.

Examples

  • Testimony about life in ancient Rome is accepted based on historical records, not firsthand verification.
  • Listening to a creationist teacher explain evolution still conveys valid knowledge.
  • Relying on a search engine to settle a debate about best-selling albums involves both testimony and cross-checking.

7. Context Shapes What We Can Know

What we “know” often depends on the setting in which we acquire the knowledge. Contextualists argue that the criteria for knowledge are flexible, varying depending on the situation we’re in.

For example, a father identifying a zebra at a trusted zoo doesn’t entertain the possibility it’s a painted donkey. This judgment might be questioned in a shadier setting. Context also explains how knowledge claims that appear contradictory—like a basketball player being described as tall by one person and average by another—can both be accurate within their respective frameworks.

Contextualism addresses such inconsistencies, showing that knowledge is filtered through situations and relevance.

Examples

  • A child trusting a zoo’s reputation to identify zebras.
  • A sports commentator comparing an athlete’s height to other players.
  • A person’s “knowledge” of wearing shoes depends on ignoring the skeptic’s alternate scenarios.

8. Humans Use Intuition for “Mind Reading”

You might instinctively know if a friend is certain about a topic or just guessing, without needing explicit cues. This ability, or epistemological “mind reading,” lets humans infer what others know through subtle clues.

Chimpanzees share some mind-reading abilities, but humans surpass them by manipulating gaps in others’ knowledge. For example, practical jokes exploit another person’s ignorance to create surprise and humor.

While impressive, intuitive mind reading has limits. We tend to overestimate how much others know, which can lead to misunderstandings in day-to-day life.

Examples

  • Guessing whether a colleague understands an email’s implications.
  • Chimpanzees assessing if others have spotted their hidden food supplies.
  • Playing tricks like offering “peanuts” from a can that contains a rubber snake.

9. Shared Knowledge Creates Collective Strength

Combining individual knowledge can lead to remarkable outcomes. For instance, an orchestra relies on each musician’s specialized skill and shared understanding of symphonic work. Together, they create a whole greater than any one person could achieve alone.

This idea extends beyond music to other areas of collaboration. Work teams, research groups, and communities all demonstrate how pooling knowledge allows us to achieve more than any individual ever could.

Shared knowledge builds connections and solves problems more efficiently, reinforcing the idea that knowledge is a communal resource.

Examples

  • An orchestra relies on musicians contributing their unique expertise to produce harmony.
  • Research teams design experiments by pooling specialized knowledge.
  • Crowdsourcing platforms gather collective wisdom to solve social challenges.

Takeaways

  1. Question everything—Start asking how you “know” what you believe and consider alternative sources of information.
  2. Collaborate—Leverage group knowledge to create solutions no one individual could achieve on their own.
  3. Trust your intuition—When assessing others’ knowledge or intent, use your natural ability to intuit mental states as a guide.

Books like Knowledge